文档库 最新最全的文档下载
当前位置:文档库 › 耶鲁大学开放课程-哲学:死亡的26课的英文字幕22

耶鲁大学开放课程-哲学:死亡的26课的英文字幕22

耶鲁大学开放课程-哲学:死亡的26课的英文字幕22
耶鲁大学开放课程-哲学:死亡的26课的英文字幕22

Death: Lecture 22 Transcript

Professor Shelly Kagan: Last time, I distinguished between two ways in which thinking about the facts about the nature of death could influence our behavior. On the one hand, it could give us reasons to behave or respond differently, and on the other hand it could merely cause us to behave differently. Insofar as it just happens to be some fact about human psychology that we behave this way or that way, perhaps the appropriate way to deal with the facts of death would be to simply disregard them. I'm inclined to believe, however, that there are ways in which thinking about the facts would not merely cause us to behave one way rather than another but give us reason to behave one way rather than another. And that's the question that I want to then explore from here on out. In what circumstances, or in what ways, should we behave one way rather than another?

So, I'm not merely going to draw on facts about how, as it happens, we behave. It could be that if you dwelled upon the facts about death, you would scream interminably until the moment you died--taking a tip from Tolstoy. But that doesn't itself show that that's an appropriate response; that might just be a mere causal fact about how we're built. The question I want to ask is, how is it appropriate, in what ways is there reason, to react one way rather than another?

Now as I say, the thought seems very compelling for most of us that there are ways in which it makes sense for the facts about death to influence how we live, what our attitudes are, what are emotions are. Kafka, for example, said the meaning of life is the fact that it ends. Nice little cryptic saying, as is typical of Kafka. But the suggestion, I suppose, is a fairly common one, that it's something deep about how we should live, that we're going to die, that our life will come to an end. And the question we want to then explore is how should the fact, how should recognizing the fact, that we're going to die, influence how we live? How should we respond to that fact? Now actually, the very first kind of behavior, quote/unquote behavior, that I want us to think about perhaps isn't strictly speaking a form of behavior at all. I rather have in mind our emotional response, because indeed one of the most common reactions to death, I suppose, is fear of death. Indeed, fear may in many cases be too weak a term--an extremely strong form of fear--terror of death is, I suppose, a very common emotional response to death. And what I want to do next is have us ask ourselves, well, is fear of death a rationally appropriate response?

Now, the crucial word here is "appropriate." I don't want to deny at all what I take to be the empirical fact that many people are afraid of death. How common a reaction that is, and how strong the fear is, I suppose that would be something for psychologists or sociologists to study. And I'm not interested in that question. I take it that fear of death is very common. I want to know, is fear of death an appropriate, a reasonable emotion?

Now, in raising that question, I'm obviously presupposing the larger philosophical thesis that it makes sense to talk about emotions as being appropriate or inappropriate. We can ask not only what emotions does somebody have, but we can also ask what emotions should they have? Now, this point perhaps isn't an obvious one, so maybe it's worth dwelling on for a moment or two, before we turn to fear of death per se.

What's another example of an emotion that's got some appropriateness conditions? So, in a moment I'll turn to asking, what are the conditions under which it's appropriate to be afraid of something?--but to make the more general point, look, take something like pride; pride's an emotion. Under what conditions does it make sense to be proud of something? Well, I suppose at least two conditions jump out. First of all, the thing that you're proud of has to be some kind of accomplishment. If you were to say to me right now, "I'm really proud of the fact that I'm breathing," I'd look at you in a noncomprehending fashion because it doesn't seem to me that breathing is difficult in any way, doesn't count as an accomplishment, and as such I can't understand how or why you would be proud of the fact that you're breathing. Now, maybe if you suffered from asthma and you had to have gone through excruciating physical therapy in order to learn how to use your lungs after some accident or something; maybe if we told a story like that we could see how breathing naturally and normally would be an accomplishment, something to be proud of. But for all of us, I presume, it's not an accomplishment; hence it's not something that it's appropriate to be proud of.

Even if we've got an accomplishment, that may not be enough. For something to be something that it makes sense for you to be proud of it, it's got to be in some way an accomplishment that reflects well on you. Now, the most straightforward cases are cases where it's your accomplishment, and the reason that pride makes sense is because you're the one who did this difficult thing. So, you got an A on your philosophy paper and you tell me that you're proud and I understand that; getting an A on a philosophy paper is an accomplishment, and if you wrote the paper then I understand why you're proud. Of course, if what you did was go on the Internet and go to one of those sites where you pay money and somebody else writes an A paper for you, well, I understand why maybe they should be proud that they've written a great philosophy paper, but I don't see how this reflects especially positively upon you. So again, there's a kind of appropriateness condition for pride, where the object or the event or the activity that you're proud of, or the feature, has to somehow reflect on you.

Now, that's not to say that it's got to be your accomplishment, at least not in any straightforward, narrow sense. It makes sense, for example, to be proud of your children's accomplishments because there's the right kind of connection between you and your children. So, in some sense it's connected to you. And we can have cases where we wonder about whether or not the connection is tight enough or what exactly the nature of the connection has to be. Perhaps as an American you took pride when the Americans win some event at the Olympics or the Tour de France or what have you, and you say to yourself, "well look, I didn't ride the bicycle but for all that I'm an American and an American won, I'm proud." And that makes sense; we can understand how you think the connection there is tight enough. On the other hand if you say, "look, the Germans won the event in the Olympics and I'm really proud," and I ask, well, are you yourself German, do you have German heritage, did you contribute to the German Olympics support team? If none of that's true, then again the appropriateness condition doesn't seem to be satisfied. It doesn't make sense to be proud.

All right, look, we could spend more time worrying about the conditions under which it makes sense to feel pride. But of course that's not really my purpose here. My purpose of bringing that in was just to try to make good on the thought that emotions do have requirements; not necessarily requirements for what you have to have in place in order to feel the emotion. It's a

harder question whether all these things need to be in place in order to feel the emotion. But at least these things need to be in place in order for it to make sense for you to have the emotion, in order for it to be rational or reasonable to feel the emotion, in order for that emotional response to be an appropriate response to your circumstances or situation.

So, let's ask ourselves, then, what are the appropriateness conditions for fear? Because armed with that set of conditions, we'll then be able to go on and ask, is it appropriate to feel fear of death? Now, three conditions come to mind when I think about this question, when I've thought about this question over the years. The first is this--and I suppose this first one's going to be fairly uncontroversial--in order to be afraid of something--even though I slipped in this, to talk about what you need to have in order to feel fear, what I really mean is in order for it to make sense to feel fear--the thing that you're afraid of has to be bad.

If somebody were to say to me, "I'm afraid that after class somebody's going to give me an ice cream cone", again I'd look at them in noncomprehension. I'd say, "Why are you afraid of that? How could it make any sense to be afraid?" And again, it's not that somebody couldn't give you an answer. They'd say, "Oh I'm trying to lose weight but I'm so weak and if they give me an ice cream cone then I'll just eat it and that'll ruin my diet for the week," well, then I'd understand. From that point of view an ice cream cone is a bad thing and so that first condition on fear would be satisfied. But if you don't have a story like that, if you're like most of us, most of the time, and an ice cream cone's a pretty good thing, a source of some passing but at least genuine pleasure, then you say, "How can you be afraid of having or getting or eating an ice cream cone?" It doesn't make sense.

To be afraid of something, it's got to be bad. It's one of the reasons why we sometimes look askance at people who have various kinds of phobias--fear of spiders or fear of dust or what have you, fear of bunnies--and you think, how does this make any sense? It's this cute little bunny; it's not dangerous. And maybe there are poisonous spiders, but most of the spiders we run across here in Connecticut are not poisonous. Fear of spiders doesn't seem appropriate. It's not that people can't have this kind of emotional reaction, it's that it doesn't make sense. Maybe it's another matter if you live in Australia, where there's poisonous snakes and spiders and other insects everyplace. All right.

So, condition number one: Fear requires something bad, as the object of your fear. I can fear getting a migraine, if I'm subject to migraines. I can't fear the pleasure of looking at a beautiful sunset. That's condition number one--bad object, something harmful. Condition number two is, there's got to be a nonnegligible chance of the bad state of affairs happening, of the bad object coming to you. It's not enough that it's a logical possibility for fear to be a reasonable reaction. There's nothing logically inconsistent or logically incoherent about the possibility that I will face my death by being ripped to pieces by Siberian tigers. It's not as though that's an inconsistent state of affairs. It's certainly logically possible, but it's so unlikely, it's so negligibly small a chance, that if anybody here is afraid that they'll be ripped to pieces by tigers, then I can only say the fear doesn't make any sense, it's not appropriate.

Again, we can tell special stories where that might be different. Suppose you tell me that, oh, when you're not a student, your work study program, what you do is, you work as an animal

trainer, or you're planning to work in the circus where you'll be training tigers, then I'll say, all right, now I suppose there's a nonnegligible chance you'll be mauled and killed by tigers. I understand it. But for the rest of us, I suppose, the chance of being killed by tigers is, well, it's not literally zero, but it's close to zero, it's negligible. And so, fear of being eaten by tigers or mauled to death by tigers doesn't make any sense.

And once you get the point, of course, it would be easy to talk about a variety of other things that the chances are so small--fear of being kidnapped by space creatures from Alpha Centauri, where I'll be taken back to the lab and they'll prod me before they dissect me alive without anesthetic. Yes, I suppose there's some possibility of that. It's not logically impossible. But again it's so vanishingly small a chance, and anybody who actually is afraid of that, the appropriate thing for us to say is that their fear is not appropriate. All right, so you need to have a chance of the bad thing, and it's got to be a large enough chance. And I suppose again there would be room for us

to argue about how large a chance is large enough, but when you have vanishingly small chances then the fear doesn't make any sense. That's condition number two.

Condition number three, I think, is somewhat more controversial, but for all that it still seems correct to me, and that's this. We need to have a certain amount of uncertainty in order to have fear be appropriate. You need to have some--it's not clear how much--but at least some significant amount of uncertainty about whether the bad thing will occur, and/or how bad the bad thing will be. To see the point, to see the relevance of this third condition, imagine that a bad thing was going to happen to you with a nonnegligible chance. Indeed, far from being so small that it's virtually not worth even considering, imagine that it's guaranteed that the bad thing is going to happen. So, there's a bad thing that's going to happen, and you know precisely how bad it is. So you've got certainty with regard to the fact that the bad thing is going to happen, and certainly with regard to the size of the bad thing. I put it to you that in circumstances like that, fear is not an appropriate emotional response.

Suppose that what happens is this. Every day you come to school, to the office, whatever it is, and you bring a bagged lunch, and you put it in the office refrigerator. And you include, along with your lunch, a dessert; let's say a cookie. And every day at one o'clock, when you go to grab your lunch out of the refrigerator, you look inside and you see somebody has stolen your cookie. Well, it's a bad thing; it's not the worst thing in the world, but it's a bad thing to have somebody steal your cookie. And furthermore, this is more than a negligible chance. So, we've got condition one, condition two in place--bad thing and a nonnegligible chance of it happening. In fact, not only is it not a negligible chance that it's happening--guaranteed, it happens day after day after day after day. Bad thing, guaranteed. And you know precisely how bad it is. I put it to you, fear in that case doesn't make any sense.

Mind you, there are other negative emotions that probably make sense, like anger and resentment. Who does this thief, whoever it is, think that he or she is, to be stealing your cookie? They don't have the right to do that! You can be angry, you can be resentful. You can be sad that you don't have a dessert, day after day after day. But you can't be afraid, because there's nothing here that it makes sense for you to be afraid of. Again, being a little sloppy, maybe you are afraid, but if so, fear doesn't make sense, when you know for a certainty that the bad thing is coming and how bad it is.

Suppose that the thief strikes at random, taking different people's desserts from different bags at different times of the week, and you never know who he or she is going to steal from. Then you might be afraid that you'll be the person whose cookie got stolen. Or if cookie seems to you too silly an example, imagine that what happens is somebody breaks into dorm rooms. There's been a thief going around various dorms on campus and stealing the computer from the dorm room. Well there, fear makes sense; you're afraid that they'll steal your computer. Bad thing, nonnegligible chance, and lack of certainty.

On the other hand, suppose what happens is, this is one of those thieves like you always have in the movies, where he's such a master thief, or she's such a master thief, that they take pride in their work, and so they announce it. They take out an ad in the Yale Daily News and they say, "On Wednesday, April 27th, I shall steal the computer from so-and-so's room." And it doesn't matter what precautions you take, something always happens, and that person's computer gets stolen. Well, again, you could be angry, you can be pissed, you can be annoyed, you can feel stupid that you didn't take adequate precautions. But when the ad appears, with your name, and that date, and all year the thief has always carried through on the announced theft, I put it to you, fear doesn't make any sense, because if you know exactly what the size of the harm is going to be, and you're guaranteed that the harm is coming, fear is no longer appropriate.

Suppose that I have a little torture machine, a little pain generator, where I put your hand down and I hook it up to the electrodes and I crank the dial and I pull the switch, and you feel an electric shock. It makes sense to feel fear what the next shock is going to feel like, if the shocks vary in their intensity. But if the machine's only got one setting, on and off, and all the shocks feel exactly the same, and I've done it for you, "so look, okay, let me show you what it feels like; it feels like that." Oh, not comfortable. Let me show you what it feels like, it feels like that; over and over, 5, 6, 7, 8 times; we're doing some sort of weird psychology experiment here. Well, you know exactly that it's coming, you know exactly what it's going to feel like. Fear, I put it to you, doesn't make any sense.

Suppose the experiment's over now, and you think--you've gotten your ten dollars and I refuse to let you go and I say, "I'm going to do it one more time, no worse than before." Well, you might not believe me and that might introduce the element of uncertainty and then perhaps fear would be appropriate. But if you believe me that one more pain exactly like the ones you felt before is coming, fear--anger makes sense, resentment makes sense, sadness that you're going to feel this pain perhaps makes sense--but fear doesn't make sense.

So, three conditions. You need to have it's something bad. You need to have on the one hand nonnegligible chance that the bad thing's going to happen, and you have to have a lack of certainty. If you've got certainty as to the nature of the bad and certainty that it's coming, then fear doesn't make sense.

One of the points probably worth mentioning in passing--even when fear does make sense, there's a kind of proportionality condition that we need to keep in mind as well. Even if there's a nonnegligible chance of the harm coming, and so fear is appropriate, it doesn't make fear appropriate if it's obsessive fear, horrendous fear, tremendous fear. Maybe some mild concern is all that's appropriate if the chances are small. Similarly, the amount of fear needs to be

proportioned to the size of the bad. That's perhaps why the cookie example, you might think a lot of fear there's not appropriate because even if it comes, how bad is it? Loss of a cookie. All right, so there are some conditions that need to be met before fear is appropriate at all, and on the other hand even when fear is appropriate, it's still legitimate to ask, how much fear is appropriate? So, armed with all of this, let's now turn to the question, is fear of death appropriate, and if so, how much? And immediately we see we need to draw some distinctions. Well, what are we supposedly being afraid of when we are afraid of death? And two or perhaps three things need to be distinguished. The first thing you might worry about is the process of dying. Some people find that the actual process at the end of their life is a painful and unpleasant one. Yes, I've given the example of being mauled to death by tigers or eaten alive by tigers. Well, I imagine that would be a pretty unpleasant way to die. And so insofar as there is some nonnegligible chance that you will die a painful death, then I suppose there's some room for some--an appropriate amount--of fear. Of course, we then have to ask, well, what is the chance that you'll die painfully? I've already indicated for people in this room I rather imagine the chance of being mauled to death by tigers is vanishingly small. So, I think, no fear of that form of painful death is appropriate. And for that matter, I've got to suggest that I suspect that fear of dying through a painful operation by the aliens from Alpha Centauri is not appropriate either.

Still, the sad fact of the matter is that there are people in the world who do suffer painful deaths, in particular, of course, because the number of diseases that might kill us off in their final stages are sometimes painful. Now, one of the interesting facts is that we could of course minimize or eliminate the pain by giving people adequate pain medication. And so, it comes as a rather unpleasant bit of news that most hospitals do not provide adequate pain medication, in many, many instances, at the end of life. Why? That's a whole other complicated question. But I suppose if somebody were to say to me that--look, I read the newspaper, there are studies done periodically about whether or not there's adequate pain medication at the end of life and the studies suggest, year after year, that no, we still don't in general provide adequate pain medication. If you were to say to me, "In light of that I've got some fear that this may happen to me," well, I'd understand that. Again, if you said to me, "I can't sleep for fear that this is going to happen to me," I'd want to say, well, that sort of fear strikes me as disproportionate.

But at any rate, I suppose that when people say that they're afraid of death, although some of them, in some moments, might have in mind, what they mean is that they're afraid of the process of dying, I take it that that's not actually the central fear that people mean to be expressing. People mean to suggest that they're afraid of death itself, they're afraid of being dead. And with regard to that, I want to suggest, I don't actually think the relevant conditions are satisfied. Look, let's think about what they were again. There was a certain amount of uncertainty. Well, of course, with regard to being dead there's no uncertainty at all. You're guaranteed that you're going to die. And indeed, condition number one, that the bad thing--for fear to make sense the object of my fear has to be a bad thing. Well, let's ask ourselves, is being dead intrinsically a bad thing? It doesn't seem to me that it is.

Of course, this all presupposes the positions about the nature of death that I argued for in the first half of this semester. There's nothing mysterious or unknown about death. Look, suppose you

thought there was. Suppose you believe in the afterlife, or at least the possibility of an afterlife, and you're worried that you might go to hell. Well, then fear makes some sense. If there's a possibility, nonnegligible in your mind, that there'll be a painful experience after you die--not guaranteed--if you're a bad enough sinner so that you're certain you're going to hell, then again I think condition number three isn't satisfied. But if like most of us you wouldn't know if you were a bad enough sinner or not, and so there's some nonnegligible chance of this bad thing, without certainly, well, somebody like that who says they're afraid of being dead, for fear that they might find themselves in hell, at least I understand that.

But on the physicalist picture where death is the end, where when your body decays there's no experience at all, then it seems to me that the first condition on fear isn't satisfied. The badness of death after all, according to the deprivation account, is the mere absence of a good. And it seems to me the mere absence of a good is not the right kind of thing to be afraid of. Suppose I give you an ice cream cone, and you like it. You wish you could have a second ice cream cone. But I don't have a second ice cream cone to share with you. So you know that after the first ice cream cone is over, you won't have a second ice cream cone. That's a pity, that's a lack of something good. And now you're telling me, "I'm afraid; I'm afraid of the fact that there will be this period after the first ice cream cone is done in which I'm not getting a second ice cream cone. I'm afraid because of the badness of deprivation of ice cream." I say to you, deprivations per se are not the kind of thing to be afraid of; they're not bad in the right kind of way.

So, if death is bad only or most centrally insofar as it's a deprivation of the good things in life, there's nothing bad there to be afraid of. Well, that doesn't mean there isn't anything here in the neighborhood. After all, we have to worry not just about the fact that we're going to die, we have to worry about when we're going to die. We might be certain that death is going to come, but

we're not certain that death is going to come a long time from now, as opposed to soon. So, perhaps the relevant thing to be afraid of is the possibility that you'll die soon.

Consider an analogy. Suppose that you're at a party, it's a great party, you wish you could stay and stay and stay, but this is taking place back in high school, and what's going to happen is your mother is going to call at a certain point and tell you it's time to go home. Now, let's just imagine there's nothing bad about being at home; it's neutral. You just wish you could stay but you know you can't. If you know the call is going to come at midnight, guaranteed, then there's nothing to be afraid of. You might resent the fact that your mother is going to call you at midnight, be annoyed at the fact that she won't let you stay out till one o'clock like your other friends, but there's nothing to be afraid of. There, it's 11 o'clock and you're saying, "I'm terrified of the fact that the call's going to come at midnight; I know it's going to come." See, fear there doesn't make sense, because it doesn't have the relevant degree of uncertainty. You know exactly what's coming and you know for a certainty that it's coming; fear isn't appropriate.

Well, suppose instead of what happens is a guarantee that your mother's going to call at midnight, what we've got is your mother's going to call sometime between 11 and 1. Now, some fear makes sense. Most of the time she calls around 12, 12:30; sometimes she calls at 1 for parties; occasionally she calls at 11. You're worried now, there's a nonnegligible chance she'll call at 11 rather than sometime later, 12 or 1 o'clock. There's a bad thing, some nonnegligible chance, and the absence of certainty. Now some degree of fear makes sense. And perhaps that's what we've

got with regard to death. If so, we might say the crucial ingredient here, by virtue of which death is something that it's appropriate for us to be afraid of is because of the unpredictability.

Even if we had variability we might not have unpredictability. That's a point that we touched upon previously. It's the unpredictability that leaves you in a position of not knowing whether death will come soon, or death will come late. Will you die at 20, will you die at 50, will you die at 80, or will you die at 100? It seems to me that if it weren't for the unpredictability, fear of death wouldn't make any sense at all. Given that we do have unpredictability, some fear of death might make sense; although again it's important to be clear about what it is that it makes sense to be afraid of. It's not being dead per se. I remain of the opinion that being dead per se is not the sort of thing it makes sense to be afraid of, once you've concluded that death is the end. The only thing that it might make some sense to be afraid of is that you might die too soon--earlier rather than later.

Of course, having noted that point, we then have to ask, well how much fear is appropriate? How great is the chance that you'll die too soon? Your fear needs to be proportioned to the likelihood. How likely is it that you will die in the next year, or five years, or for that matter 10 or 20 years? The fact of the matter is for most of you, almost all of you, the chances are very unlikely indeed; not quite negligible, but rather small. For a healthy 20-year-old, for example, the chances of dying in the next five or ten years are extremely small, in which case even if some slight fear might be called for, no significant amount of fear seems called for. So, if somebody were to say to me, "look, the facts about death are so overwhelming that I'm terrified of death," all I can say in response is not, that I don't believe you, but for all that it seems to me terror of death is not an appropriate response. It doesn't make sense given the facts.

Now, having said that, that doesn't mean that there may not be some other emotion, some other negative emotion that is appropriate. Fear of death strikes me as, for the most part, overblown;

it's widespread, I suppose, but for the most part inappropriate. But that doesn't mean that--As I suggested before in working through some of these examples, sometimes anger makes sense; sometimes resentment makes sense; sorrow, regret, sadness, that may make sense. So, in having argued that for the most part fear of death does not make sense, I haven't yet given us any reason to think that there might not be other emotions, negative emotions, that do make sense. So let's ask. What about some of those other possible emotions?

What negative emotion, if any, does it make sense to feel about death itself, the fact that you're going to die? Well, of course, look, it's also worth bearing in mind, since I've argued that immortality would be bad, the fact that you will die is not actually bad. It's good because it saves you from the unpleasant aspect of an eternal, dreary, dreadful immortal existence. Still, we might say, most of us, almost all of us, die too soon. So, what about that? We die before life has yielded up all the goods that it could have given us. So what is the appropriate negative emotional response here? Or is there one?

I suppose the natural second suggestion is anger. You might say, look, maybe fear isn't right,

isn't appropriate, but anger. I'm angry. I want to shake my fist at the universe and curse the universe for giving me only 50 years or 70 years or 80 years even 100 years, when the world is

such a rich, incredibly fantastic place that it would take thousands of years or longer to exhaust what it has to offer. So, isn't anger an appropriate response?

And again, I think the answer is not so clear that it is, because, like all the other emotions, anger itself has appropriateness conditions. In order for anger to make sense, well, here's condition number one. It seems to me it's got to be directed at a person, it's got to be directed at an agent,

it's got to be directed at some thing that had some choice over what it was doing to you. So, when your roommate, whatever it is, spills coffee on your computer, destroying the hard drive or whatever it is, because they were careless, even though you told them previously to be more careful, anger makes sense. It's directed at your roommate, who's a person, who had some control over what they were doing. Your roommate's an agent. If you want to get angry at me for the grades that you receive in this class, well, at least condition number one makes sense; you're directing your anger at an agent, at an individual person who has some control over how I behave, how they behave.

Condition number two, I suppose--this may not be all the conditions, but at least a second one is--anger makes sense when, and only when, the agent has wronged you, has treated you in a way that it was morally inappropriate for them to teat you. If your roommate has been doing things that you don't like, but they haven't done anything wrong, anger doesn't make sense. When you are angry at them, you are revealing the fact that you think they've mistreated you. Mistreatment requires the notion of they've behaved toward you in a way that morally they shouldn't. All right, these strike me as two conditions that need to be in place in order for anger to be an appropriate emotional response.

Of course, again, we no doubt feel anger in other cases, although typically when we're angry at inanimate objects it's because we've personified them. Your paper is due, you're rushing off to class, you're about to print it out, and your computer crashes, and you get angry at the computer. Well, what's going on there, I suppose, is you've personified the computer. You have fallen into the trap, understandable, natural, of viewing the computer as though it was a person who had deliberately chosen to fail right now, letting you down yet again. And I understand this sort of behavior; I do this sort of thing as well. But of course you can step back. At least, once your anger has subsided, you can step back and say, look, getting angry at your computer doesn't really make sense, because your computer is not a person; your computer is not an agent; your computer didn't have any choice or control.

Suppose that--take those two conditions and now ask ourselves, does it make sense then to be angry at the fact that we're going to die? And I suppose the answer is going to be, well, look, who is it, or what is it that you think is the cause of our mortality, or the fact that we only get our 50 or 80 years? Here's two crude, basic alternatives. You might believe in God, a kind of classic, theistic, conception of God, according to which God is a person who makes decisions about what to do. And God has condemned us to death. That's what happens in Genesis, God punishes Adam and Eve by making them die. All right, that's picture number one. Picture number two is you just think there's this impersonal universe, atoms swirling in the void, coming together in various combinations, but there's no person behind the scene controlling all of it.

Let's consider the two possibilities. Possibility number one, God. Well, look, if you've got the God view, at least we satisfy the first of our appropriateness conditions. We can say, look; we can say, I'm angry at God for condemning us to a life that's short, that's so inadequate, relative to the riches that the world offers us. That's condition number one. But what about condition number two? Condition number two, after all, requires that God has mistreated us in giving us our 50 or 80 or 100 years. And is that the case? Has God wronged us? Has God treated us in some way that isn't morally justified? If not, anger at God, resentment of God, wouldn't make sense.

Suppose your roommate comes into the suite and has a box of candy, and he gives you a piece of candy, and you enjoy it. And he gives you a second piece of candy and you enjoy it. And he gives you a third piece of candy and you enjoy it. And you ask for a fourth piece of candy, and he won't give it you. Has he wronged you? Has he treated you immorally? Does he owe you more candy? It's not clear that he or she does. But if not, then being angry--again, I would certainly understand it if you got angry, in the sense that it's a perfectly common enough response. But is anger an appropriate response to your roommate for giving you something, and then not giving you more? It's not clear that it is an appropriate response. The appropriate response actually seems to me to be, not one of anger, but gratitude. Your roommate didn't owe you any candy at all, and they gave you four pieces, or whatever it was, the number just was. You might wish you could have more, you might be sad that you can't have more, but anger doesn't seem appropriate. God doesn't, as far as I can see, owe it to us to give us more life than what we get.

Well, suppose we don't believe in the God theory but the universe theory. Well then, of

course ,even condition number one isn't satisfied. The universe is not a person, is not an agent, has no choice and control. And as such, again, it just seems to me that anger then--I can lift my fist and curse the universe; of course, what I'm doing then is, I'm personifying the universe, treating the universe as though it was a person that deliberately decided to make us die too soon. But however common that response might be, it makes no sense rationally if the universe is not a person. It's just atoms swirling, forming various kinds of combinations. Anger at the fact that I'm going to die, or die too soon, doesn't make sense either.

Well, what about sorrow? Maybe I should just be sad at the fact that I'm going to die too soon. And I think some emotion along that line does make sense. The world's a wonderful place. It would be better to have more of it. I'm sad that I don't get more, that I'm not going to get more. But having had that thought, I immediately find myself with another thought. Although it's a pity I don't get more, I'm extremely lucky to have gotten as much as I get. The universe is just this swirling mass of atoms, forming clumps of various kinds of things, and dissolving. Most of those atoms don't get to be alive at all. Most of those atoms don't get to be a person, falling in love, seeing sunsets, eating ice cream. It's extraordinarily lucky of us to be in this select, fortunate few. Let me close then with an expression of this thought. This is from Kurt Vonnegut's book, Cat's Cradle. This is a kind of prayer that one of the characters in the novel says--is supposed to say--at the deathbed.

God made mud.

God got lonesome.

So God said to some of the mud, "Sit up."

"See all I've made," said God. "The hills, the sea, the sky, the stars."

And I, with some of the mud, had got to sit up and look around.

Lucky me, lucky mud.

I, mud, sat up and saw what a nice job God had done.

Nice going God!

Nobody but you could have done it God! I certainly couldn't have.

I feel very unimportant compared to You.

The only way I can feel the least bit important is to think of all the mud that didn't even get to sit up and look around.

I got so much, and most mud got so little.

Thank you for the honor!

Now mud lies down again and goes to sleep.

What memories for mud to have!

What interesting other kinds of sitting-up mud I met!

I loved everything I saw [Vonnegut 1963].

It seems to me that the right emotional response isn't fear, it isn't anger, it's gratitude that we're able to be alive at all.

---

References

Vonnegut, Kurt. 1963. Cat's Cradle.

耶鲁大学公开课:博弈论全集下载

导论-五个入门结论 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/3413394658.html,/movie/2011/12/Q/2/S7KDBTEQ2.flv 2: 学会换位思考 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/3413394658.html,/movie/2011/12/Q/L/S7KDC64QL.flv 3: 迭代剔除和中位选民定理 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/3413394658.html,/movie/2011/12/J/Q/S7KDBUDJQ.flv 4: 足球比赛与商业合作之最佳对策 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/3413394658.html,/movie/2011/12/6/0/S7KDC7960.flv 5: 纳什均衡之坏风气与银行挤兑 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/3413394658.html,/movie/2011/12/6/R/S7KDCAC6R.flv 6: 纳什均衡之约会游戏与古诺模型 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/3413394658.html,/movie/2011/12/5/E/S7KDB145E.flv 7: 纳什均衡伯川德模型与选民投票 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/3413394658.html,/movie/2011/12/4/1/S7KDCB541.flv 8: 立场选择种族隔离与策略随机化 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/3413394658.html,/movie/2011/12/D/D/S7KDBQ6DD.flv 9: 混合策略及其在网球比赛中的应用

https://www.wendangku.net/doc/3413394658.html,/movie/2011/12/E/7/S7KDBUFE7.flv 10: 混合战略棒球,约会和支付您的税 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/3413394658.html,/movie/2011/12/F/0/S7KDC3GF0.flv 11: 合作,突变,与平衡 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/3413394658.html,/movie/2011/12/B/E/S7KDEBLBE.flv 12: 社会公约,侵略,和周期 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/3413394658.html,/movie/2011/12/2/J/S7KDE8L2J.flv 13: 道德风险,奖励和饥饿的狮子 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/3413394658.html,/movie/2011/12/1/P/S7KDED31P.flv 14: 承诺,间谍,和先行者优势 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/3413394658.html,/movie/2011/12/L/T/S7KDEAKLT.flv 15: 国际象棋,战略和可信的威胁 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/3413394658.html,/movie/2011/12/T/4/S7KDEENT4.flv 16: 声誉和决斗 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/3413394658.html,/movie/2011/12/6/F/S7KDEFS6F.flv 17: 最后通牒和讨价还价 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/3413394658.html,/movie/2011/12/A/T/S7KDEK0A T.flv 18:

哈佛大学公开课《公平与正义》第2集中英文字幕

Funding for this program is provided by: 本节目的赞助来自...... Additi onal funding provided by: 另外的赞助来自…… Last time, we argued about 上次,我们谈到 the case of The Quee n v. Dudley & Stephe ns, 女王诉Dudley和Stephens案件, the lifeboat case, the case of cann ibalism at sea. 那个救生艇上,海上吃人的案件. And with the argume nts about the lifeboat in mind, 带着针对这个案件所展开的一些讨论 the argume nts for and aga inst what Dudley and Stephe ns did in mind, 带着支持和反对Dudley和Stephens所做的吃人行为的讨论 let's turn back to the philosophy, the utilitaria n philosophy of Jeremy Ben tham. 让我们回头来看看Bentham的功利主义哲学. Ben tham was born in En gla nd in 1748. At the age of 12, he went to Oxford. Bentham于1748年出生于英国.12岁那年,他去了牛津大学 At 15, he went to law school. He was admitted to the Bar at age 19 15岁时,他去了法学院.19岁就取得了律师资格 but he n ever practiced law. 但他没有从事于律师行业.

《耶鲁大学开放课程:金融市场》(Open Yale course:Financial Markets)课程目录及下载地址(不断更新中)

《耶鲁大学开放课程:金融市场》(Open Yale course:Financial Markets) 简介

★小羊羊村长★大学开发课程粉丝Q群:122798308 课程类型:金融 课程简介: 金融机构是文明社会的重要支柱。它们为投资活动提供支持及风险管理。如果我们想要预测金融机构动态及他们在这个信息时代中的发展态势,我们必须对其业务有所了解。本课程将涉及的内容有:金融学理论、金融业的发展历程、金融机构(例如银行、保险公司、证券公

司、期货公司及其他衍生市场)的优势与缺陷以及这些机构的未来发展前景。 课程结构: 本课程每讲75分钟,一周两次,在2008年春季录制并收入耶鲁大学公开课程系列。 关于教授罗伯特希勒 Robert J. Shiller是Yale大学Arthur M. Okun经济学讲座教授和Yale大学管理学院国际金融中心研究员. Shiller教授的研究领域包括行为金融学和房地产,并在“金融经济学杂志”,“美国经济评论”,“金融学杂志”,“华尔街杂志”和“金融时报”等著名刊物发表文章. 主要著作包括“市场波动”,“宏观市场”(凭借此书他获得了TIAA-CREF的保罗 A. 萨缪尔森奖),“非理性繁荣和金融新秩序:二十一世纪的风险”

Robert J. Shiller is Arthur M. Okun Professor of Economics at Yale University and a Fellow at the International Center for Finance at the Yale School of Management. Specializing in behavioral finance and real estate, Professor Shiller has published in Journal of Financial Economics, American Economic Review, Journal of Finance, Wall Street Journal, and Financial Times. His books include Market V olatility, Macro Markets (for which he won the TIAA-CREF's Paul A. Samuelson Award), Irrational Exuberance and The New Financial Order: Risk in the Twenty-First Century. 目录: 1.Finance and Insurance as Powerful Forces in Our Economy and Society 金融和保险在我们经济和社会中的强大作用 2. The Universal Principle of Risk Management: Pooling and the Hedging of Risks 风险管理中的普遍原理:风险聚集和对冲 3. Technology and Invention in Finance 金融中的科技与发明 4. Portfolio Diversification and Supporting Financial Institutions (CAPM Model) 投资组合多元化和辅助性的金融机构(资本资产定价模型) 5. Insurance: The Archetypal Risk Management Institution 保险:典型的风险管理制度 6. Efficient Markets vs. Excess V olatility 有效市场与过度波动之争 7. Behavioral Finance: The Role of Psychology

耶鲁公开课笔记4

美国耶鲁大学网络公开课《金融市场》视频笔记4 耶鲁大学网络公开课《金融市场》由罗伯特.J.希勒(Robert J. Shiller)教授主讲。共26课(集),每课时长均为一个多小时,配有字幕。 [第4课] 多元化投资组合和辅助性的金融机构(时长1小时07分) 本课内容是多元化投资组合(Portfolio Diversification),辅助性的金融机构(Supporting Financial Institutions),尤其是共同基金(Mutual Funds)。 希勒介绍,这也是他长期研究的一类课题。 希勒相信,世界需要更多的多元化投资组合。这也许会让人们觉得有点怪,但希勒认为这是绝对正确的。 埃米特.汤普森也研究过这类起因的相同课题,即,为了帮助世界上的穷人,可以通过多元化投资组合来改进。 希勒说他完全就是这样认为的。 (世界上)有大量的人类困难,都可以通过多元化(分散)投资来解决。 本课要讲的,不仅只适用于安逸的富人,而对每一个人都适用。 实际上这还是关于风险的问题。 当任何人遇到惨境时,那都是某些随机遇到的结果。 当人们在生活中陷入实际麻烦时,那是由于一系列糟糕事件将人们推到不幸的境地。 金融风险管理常常就是防止发生这种不幸情况的部分(措施)。 本节课将从一些数学问题讲起,是对第二节课的继续。 希勒在第二节课讲过关于风险分摊的原理,今天接着拓展到某些方面,即,将略微集中到投资组合问题。 先讲怎样构建一个投资组合,其中有哪些数学问题,由此引入到资产定价模型,这个模型是金融中许多思考的基石。 关于这一部分内容,在耶鲁的其他课程会讲得详细些,尤其像约翰.吉纳科普洛斯(John Geanakoplos)讲的经济类251号课程(Econ 251)。 从这节课可以获得基本要点。下面从基本概念开始讲。 希勒说他只用最简单的术语来讲述。 1

片尾字幕中英文对照(20200523203533)

co-production 联合拍摄 production摄制 Consultant 策划 project supervisor专案主管 executive producer执行监制 senior producer总监制 assiatant producer助理监制 Post-Production Supervisor 后期制片监制人P roducer 制片人 Production Controller 制片总监P roduction Director 监制人 Production Supervisor 制片监制C o-Producer 联合制片人 Associate Producer 助理制片人E xecutive Producer 执行制片 Produced by制作人production co-ordinator/continuity外联制片/场记 location manager 外联制片 production administration 行政制作 administration supervisor行政主管 marketing producer制片主任 production manager制片 production secreary制作秘书 production accountant制作会计 unit manager 项目经理c lapper 场记板 Chief Director 总导演 Director 导演A ssistant Director 助理导演Associate Director 副导演 Shooting Script 分镜头剧本O riginal Story 原著A dapted by 改编B ased on X’s Y (电影)根据X(作家)的Y(小说)改编W riter编剧 Written by / Scripted by 编剧 screenplay by 编剧 script translation 剧本翻译 english subtitles by英文字幕翻译 Conducted by 指挥 Director of Photography 总摄影C inematography摄影C inematography by 摄影A ssociate Director of Photography 副摄影师C utter 剪辑师M ontage 剪辑(蒙太奇 Film Editing剪辑first cameta assistant 副摄影师 camera assistant摄影助理 Fireworks 烟火Lighting 灯光,照明lighting assistant 灯光助理

国外一些大学的公开课

一个偶然的机会在verycd上发现了耶鲁大学的公开课,下载了哲学死亡,古希腊文明和聆听音乐等课程来听,感觉很不错。对于我们这些无钱出国的人来说,能够免费的享受到如此丰厚的知识和思想的盛宴,真的得感谢这个信息通达的互联网时代。在网上搜集资源的时候,发现这篇报道总结的还不错,转来给大家共享吧。 目前网上的公开课包括哈佛、耶鲁、麻省理工、伯克利分校、卡耐基梅隆等名校。在配有字幕的课程中,最受欢迎的是哈佛的《公正》,耶鲁的《1648—1945的欧洲文明》《哲学:死亡》《1945年后的美国小说》《金融市场》《聆听音乐》《博弈论》《基础物理》《心理学导论》等。后者的课程翻译过来较多,是因为耶鲁的资源更丰富,比如字幕、课件等。 如果你英文足够好,可以将听课范围进一步扩大,直接登录这些名校的网站。 哈佛大学 部分课程对全球开放,目前首选就是Justice(公正)这门课,共12节。感兴趣的人可以通过https://www.wendangku.net/doc/3413394658.html,网站,免费观看或下载。 加州大学伯克利分校 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/3413394658.html,/courses.php。作为美国第一的公立大学,伯克利分校提供了人类学、生物、化学、历史等十几类学科的几百门公开课。伯克利的视频都是.rm格式,请注意转换格式。 麻省理工学院 设立了OpenCourse网站https://www.wendangku.net/doc/3413394658.html,/OcwWeb/web/home/home/index.htm,把1900门课免费提供给全世界。提供大量课程课件,只有少数视频讲座。 耶鲁大学 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/3413394658.html,/,到今年秋天,预计放在网上的课程将达到36门。 卡耐基梅隆 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/3413394658.html,/oli/,卡耐基梅隆针对初入大学的大学生,提供10门学科的课程视频。 英国公开大学 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/3413394658.html,/course/index.php,英国十几所大学联合起来,组建了英国公开大学。有一部分课程是对注册学生开放的,还有一批课程是免费的,并提供视频。 约翰霍普金斯

耶鲁大学开放课程《古希腊历史简介》(全24集)

耶鲁大学开放课程《古希腊历史简介》(全24集) 讲师介绍: 名称:Donald Kagan 职业:耶鲁大学经典与历史学院教授 学位:俄亥俄州立大学博士学位 唐纳德卡根是耶鲁大学经典与历史学院Sterling教授。耶鲁大学的前院长,他在1958年从俄亥俄州立大学获得博士学位博士。他的著作包括Archidamian战争,尼西阿斯和平和西西里远征,伯里克利和关于战争的起源与维护和平,和伯罗奔尼撒战争中雅典帝国的诞生。2002年,他是全国人文奖章获得人,2005年被任命为国家人文基金会杰斐逊讲师。About Professor Donald Kagan Donald Kagan is Sterling Professor of Classics and History at Yale University. A former dean of Yale College, he received his Ph.D. in 1958 from The Ohio State University. His publications include The Archidamian War, The Peace of Nicias and the Sicilian Expedition, Pericles and the Birth of the Athenian Empire, On the Origins of War and the Preservation of Peace, and The Peloponnesian War. In 2002 he was the recipient of the National Humanities Medal and in 2005 was named the National Endowment for the Humanities Jefferson Lecturer.

耶鲁大学公开课《死亡》详细笔记

PHIL 176 Death Professor Shelly Kagan (第一课没什么实质内容,可以略过)教授在第一课列举了这门课将要讨论的一些问题:1.人能否幸免于死2.人是什么?“我”是什么?3.有没有来生?4.自杀一定是恶的吗?……然后他摆出了自己的观点:1.不存在灵魂2.永生并不是好事情3.对死亡的恐惧是很正常的4.自杀在特定情境下有可能是理性的,并且在道德上是正当的…… 他希望通过这门课:学生能够自己独立思考。他不是要灌输给学生这些观点,而是要引导学生运用自己的理性,无论是支持还是反对这些观点,都要有合理的根据,给出论证。 第二课 要回答“我能否幸免于死”“我死后我是否还存在”,就需要先回答:“我”是什么?或人是什么?什么叫“幸免于死”?什么叫“活着”?一个人过了一段时间仍然是这个人,这是怎么一回事?…… 反驳:有人认为这个问题是混淆概念造成的,根本毫无意义,因为1.如果“死亡”的意思是生命的结束的话,那么2.“是否来生”就相当于“生命结束之后是否还有生命”,这就好比“碗里的饭吃完后碗里还有饭吗”,那么3.“是否有来生”或“我能否幸免与死”的答案当然就是否定的(因为很明显这些提问自相矛盾),这能从问题里直接得到答案。△回应:1.如果,“死亡”指的是身体的死亡(即一系列的生理过程);那么,2.之前的问题将变成“我的身体死后我是否还存在”,这和“生命结束之后是否还有生命”不同,不能从提问中直接得到答案。YYets 3.所以,在这个意义上提问和回答“我能否幸免与死”是有意义的。 要回答“我能否幸免于死”(在上面的那个理解下),就需要先弄清楚:“我”是什么?“我”是什么东西组成的?或者人是什么?人由什么组成? 一般来说,有两种主流观点:一、二元论(Dualism)◎1.人是由身体和心灵(灵魂)两部分组合而成严格说来,人的本质是灵魂,它与某具肉身密切联系着;“我”就是指我的灵魂,尽管与我的身体紧密联系着。2.身体和心灵是完全不同的两种东西,身体是物质的,灵魂是非物质的(不是由原子、分子构成的)3.心灵指挥身体,“身体反作用于心灵”4.死亡就是指身体的死亡,灵魂离开肉体(?)二、物理主义(Physicalism)○1.人只有身体,尽管2.这个身体能够实现多种功能3.人就是一个物理对象,一个纯物质的存在4.谈论心灵,实际上就是谈论大脑(或大脑的功能),正如微笑就是特殊的肌肉运动5.死亡就是指身体丧失了正常功能 第三课 二元论与物理主义的分歧:是否存在灵魂? 证明事物存在的方法:1.通过五感获得的经验证据来证明但是,灵魂是非物质的(如果二元论正确的话),我们无法通过感官来感觉到灵魂。所以2.对于无法通过五感感觉到的事物,需要通过“最佳解释推理”来证明其存在:我们必须假设a 存在,才能解释现象P,而且能给出最佳解释。(例如:原子、X 射线)注意:这里要求的是可能的“最佳”解释,而非任一看似可行的解释。 所以,二元论者要论证灵魂存在,就必须:找到我们身上的某个现象或特性F,只有通过假设灵魂存在才能给出最佳解释(物理主义无法解释或者只能给出较差的解释)。 灵魂存在论证◎YYets 根据F 的不同,有不同种类的论证。第一类诉诸普通的事物(情感、理性之类);第二类诉

最适合学习英语的50部影片及获得方法(双语4字幕可切换)

最适合学习英语的50部影片及获得方法(双语4字幕可切换) 一、视频特点: ●内容:最适合学英语的50部高清英语动画片是选用当前最流行、最经典的迪士尼等原版动画为英语 教材,给立志学好英语的小朋友提供一个良好的学习氛围,寓教于乐,使小朋友们在欢声笑语中学会英语,讲好英语!为孩子的明日的辉煌打下坚实的基础,是孩子成材的好朋友!(当然也适合成人学习、观看) ●格式:每部动画均为真正的高清节目,MKV格式,文件大小为2-4G,第一辑50部动画电影总容量为 115G。传统rmvb,清晰度不高,而且字幕有些是内嵌的,无法切换,mkv是高清720P,1080P常用格式。本人亲测在37寸电视上有非常好的清晰效果。 ●播放:电脑上,一般播放软件都可以播放;智能电视上,具体看电视型号,您可看下电视说明,或找 个.mkv格式的视频试一下;硬盘播放器;蓝光DVD机。普通DVD碟机和普通平板电视不支持,如想在普通平板电视上播放,先将动画资料复制到电脑中,再用一根高清数据线将笔记本电脑与电视机连接播放,可以实现同等功能。 ●配音:2种配音随意切换,英语配音/国语配音(双语可切换)。 ●字幕:4种字幕随意切换,中英同显/英文独显/中文独显/关闭无字幕 ●剧本:每部影片都为您配有剧本,可供您编辑后打印使用,格式为.txt,可放在手机等设备当做电子 书使用,随时当口语材料练习。 二、获得方法 ●淘宝网购买:在淘宝网上有卖,最便的80多块钱。省时间就等于省钱,个人觉得花点钱,省时间值 得。为了让买家能最实惠的拿到片源,他们简化包装,用普通DVD刻录,50级部要30多DVD,DVD的成本就近60元,而且还会刻坏一些光盘。您看两次电影也得个80元吧,而购买本商品后,没有广告、不分时间。你可以想什么时间看就什么时间看。 ●网上下载,省钱:如果这点钱您也不愿意花,而且网速快的话。提供个好方法,下载vod播放器,在 搜索里输入电影名,一般都能找到,不过这种双语4字幕的就不好找了。可一边看,一边下载。看完也下载完了。 三、播放说明 ●切换配音:以暴风影音为例 播放时鼠标在界面上滑动右上角会出现画、音、字、播4个字。其中音是对配音进行设置,字是对字幕时行设置。 ●设置字幕: 如上述,点击“字”,再点选择,就可有多种字幕供选择。而且在字体里面还可设置,字体格式和大小。四、内容展示 第一辑 50部

耶鲁公开课笔记2

美国耶鲁大学网络公开课《金融市场》视频笔记2 耶鲁大学网络公开课《金融市场》由罗伯特.J.希勒(Robert J. Shiller)教授主讲。共26课(集),每课时长均为一个多小时,配有字幕。 [第2课] 风险管理中的普遍原理:风险汇聚和对冲(时长1小时09分) 本课主题是风险管理中的普遍原理----风险汇聚和对冲(Pooling and Hedging of Risk)。 希勒认为这是金融理论中最基本、最核心的概念。 本课先讲概率论(Probability Theory),再讲通过风险汇聚来分摊风险的概念。 概率论是极具智慧的构想,诞生于历史上的特定时期,并令人意想不到地获得广泛应用,金融是其应用领域之一。 对部分学生来说,本课相对所讲的其他课会显出更多的技术性,并且遗憾的是又安排在学期初。 对于学过概率和统计的学生而言,就不是新知识了。这是从数学角度的看法。 概率论是新知识,但不要太畏惧。课前有个学生告诉希勒,他的数学有些生疏了,是否还能选这门课?希勒说,如果你能听懂这堂课,那就不会有问题。 什么是概率?通过举例说明。 比如,今年股票市场会走高的概率是多少?例如认为概率是0.45,是因为对股市悲观,预测股市会走高的可能性是45%,而股市会走平或走低的可能性是55%。这就是概率。 听了这个例子,人们就会觉得这个概念是熟悉的,如果有人提到概率是0.55或0.45,也就知道他说的意思了。 话锋一转,希勒强调,概率并非总是以这种方式来表述的。 概率论成形于十七世纪,此前没有人提出过。撰写概率论历史的作者伊恩.哈金(Ian Hacking),查遍世界所有关于概率论的文献,没有发现在十七世纪之前有概率论的文献,也就是说,在十七世纪产生了一次智慧的飞跃,当时用概率词汇来表述非常时髦,引用概率进行表述的方式很快传遍世界。 但是,有意思的是,如此简单的概念此前从未使用过。下面希勒详细介绍哈金的成果。 哈金研究表明,概率词汇早已存在于英语中,莎士比亚就用过,但其所代表的意思是什么呢?哈金举了一个年轻小姐的例子,这位小姐描述她喜欢的男子,说道,“我太喜欢他了,我觉得他有很大‘可能’”(probable)。 1

哈佛大学公开课《公平与正义》第2集中英文字幕

Funding for this program is provided by……Additional funding provided by……Last time,we argued aboutthe case ofThe Queen v. Dudley & Stephens,the lifeboat case,the case of cannibalism at sea.And with the arguments about the lifeboat in mind,the arguments for and against what Dudley and Stephens did in mind,let's turn back to the philosophy,the utilitarian philosophy of Jeremy Bentham.Bentham was born in England in 1748.At the age of 12, he went to Oxford.At 15, he went to law school.He was admitted to the Bar at age 19 but he never practiced law.Instead, he devoted his life to jurisprudence and moral https://www.wendangku.net/doc/3413394658.html,st time, we began to considerBentham's version of utilitarianism.The main idea is simply stated and it's this:The highest principle of morality,whether personal or political morality,is to maximize the general welfare,or the collective happiness,or the overall balance of pleasure over pain;in a phrase, maximize utility.Bentham arrives at this principle by the following line of reasoning:We're all governed by pain and pleasure,they are our sovereign masters,and so any moral system has to take account of them.How best to take account?By maximizing.And this leads to the principle of the greatest good for the greatest number.What exactly should we maximize?Bentham tells us happiness,or more precisely, utility -maximizing utility as a principle not only for individuals but also for

耶鲁大学公开课

甭看名人励志演讲了,去看看耶鲁大学的公开课吧(中文字幕),能学到太多了,国内的大学真是误国误民啊。。。转来当日志收着来源:陈俐彤小C~的日志 最近一朋友和我讲,YALE大学把他们上课的内容录了下来,并发布在因特网上,供网络传播浏览。 一个全世界排名第二的大学,竟然把自己课程的内容完全录了下来,并在全世界传播,在大学产业化的中国,有些人会觉得不可思议,你没交学费,怎么可以把我的课程免费的给公众提供呢?可是人家并不是这样认为的,本着人不分贵贱,教育不分你我的原则,耶鲁大学做出了这个匪夷所思的举动,实在是非常钦佩。。。 好了,不说大话,这个公开课真的非常的好,我有义务分享给我的朋友们 首先你得会用电驴,具体怎么用百度去 ps:我分享的这个是有字幕的,而且这个字幕是非常考究的,所以出的非常慢,理解一下。。。 =========================================== 音乐学 聆听音乐Listening to Music(教授本人著述) 课程简介: 本课程培养在对西方音乐理解基础上对音乐的感悟。它会介绍各种类型的音乐是如何搭配,并教导如何聆听各种类型的音乐,从巴赫,莫扎特,格里高利咏叹调到蓝调 关于课程主讲人: Craig Wright在1966年于the Eastman School获得钢琴乐和音乐史双学位,在1972年于哈佛大学获得博士学位。 Craig Wright从1973年开始在耶鲁大学任教,目前是the Henry L. and Lucy G的音乐教授。 在耶鲁大学,Craig Wright的成就包括常年流行的入门课程“聆听音乐”和选择性研讨会“探索大自然的天才”。 每年夏天,他都会带领一些耶鲁大学的社团区法国,德国和意大利采风。

哈佛公开课-公正课中英字幕_第一课

制作人:心舟 QQ:1129441083 第一讲《杀人的道德侧面》 这是一门讨论公正的课程This is a course about justice 我们以一则故事作为引子and we begin with a story. 假设你是一名电车司机\Suppose you're the driver of a trolley car 你的电车以60英里小时的速度\and your trolley car is hurtling down the track 在轨道上飞驰\at 60 miles an hour. 突然发现在轨道的尽头\And at the end of the track you notice 有五名工人正在施工\five workers working on the track. 你无法让电车停下来\You try to stop but you can't 因为刹车坏了\your brakes don't work. 你此时极度绝望\You feel desperate 因为你深知\because you know 如果电车撞向那五名工人\that if you crash into these five workers 他们全都会死\they will all die. 假设你对此确信无疑\Let's assume you know that for sure. 你极为无助\And so you feel helpless 直到你发现在轨道的右侧until you notice that there is off to the right 有一条侧轨\ a side track 而在侧轨的尽头\and at the end of that track 只有一名工人在那施工\there is one worker working on the track. 而你的方向盘还没坏\Your steering wheel works 只要你想\so you can turn the trolley car 就可以把电车转到侧轨上去\if you want to onto the side track 牺牲一人挽救五人性命\killing the one but sparing the five. 下面是我们的第一个问题:\Here's our first question: 何为正确的选择\what's the right thing to do? 换了你会怎么做\What would you do? 我们来做个调查\Let's take a poll. 有多少人会把电车开到侧轨上去\How many would turn the trolley car onto the side track? 请举手\Raise your hands. 有多少人会让电车继续往前开\How many wouldn't? How many would go straight ahead? 选择往前开的请不要把手放下\Keep your hands up those of you who would go straight ahead. 只有少数人选择往前开\A handful of people would 绝大多数都选择转弯\the vast majority would turn. 我们先来听听大家的说法\Let's hear first 探究一下为何\now we need to begin to investigate the reasons 你们会认为这是正确的选择\why you think it's the right thing to do. 先从大多数选择了转向侧轨的同学开始\Let's begin with those in the majority who

哈佛大学公开课《公正:该如何做是好》:全五课:英文字幕

THE MORAL SIDE OF MURDER This is a course about justice and we begin with a story. Suppose you're the driver of a trolley car, and your trolley car is hurtling down the track at 60 miles an hour. And at the end of the track you notice five workers working on the track. You try to stop but you can't, your brakes don't work. You feel desperate because you know that if you crash into these five workers, they will all die. Let's assume you know that for sure. And so you feel helpless until you notice that there is, off to the right, a side track and at the end of that track, there is one worker working on the track. Your steering wheel works, so you can turn the trolley car, if you want to, onto the side track killing the one but sparing the five. Here's our first question: what's the right thing to do? What would you do? Let's take a poll. How many would turn the trolley car onto the side track? Raise your hands. How many wouldn't? How many would go straight ahead? Keep your hands up those of you who would go straight ahead. A handful of people would, the vast majority would turn. Let's hear first, now we need to begin to investigate the reasons why you think it's the right thing to do. Let's begin with those in the majority who would turn to go onto the side track. Why would you do it? What would be your reason? Who's willing to volunteer a reason? Go ahead. Stand up. Because it can't be right to kill five people when you can only kill one person instead. It wouldn't be right to kill five if you could kill one person instead. That's a good reason. That's a good reason. Who else? Does everybody agree with that reason? Go ahead. Well I was thinking it's the same reason on 9/11 with regard to the people who flew the plane into the Pennsylvania field as heroes because they chose to kill the people on the plane and not kill more people in big buildings. So the principle there was the same on 9/11. It's a tragic circumstance but better to kill one so that five can live, is that the reason most of you had, those of you

(完整版)耶鲁公开课--博弈论笔记

耶鲁公开课一博弈论笔记 第一节、 名词解释 优势策略(Dominant strategy ):不论其他局中人采取什么策略,优势策略对一个局中人而言都是最好的策略。 即某些时候它胜于其他策略,且任何时候都不会比其他策略差。 注:1、"优势策略”的优势是指你的这个策略对你的其他策略占有优势,而不是无论对手采用什么策略,都占有优势的策略。 2、采用优势策略得到的最坏的结果不一定比采用另外一个策略得到的最佳的结果略胜一筹。 严格劣势策略(strictly dominated strategy):被全面的严格优势策略压住的那个策略, 也就是说不是严格优势策略以外的策略。 弱劣势策略:原来不是严格劣势策略,但是经过剔除严格劣势策略后,这个策略就成了严格 劣势策略。 例:囚徒困境 甲沉默{合作)甲认罪(背叛 乙沉默(合作)二人同服刑半年甲即时获释!乙眼刑F评 乙认罪(背扳)甲腮刑10年;乙即时获释二炯服刑2年 囚徒到底应该选择哪一项策略,才能将自己个人的刑期缩至最短?两名囚徒由于隔绝监禁,并不知道对方选择;而即使他们能交谈,还是未必能够尽信对方不会反口。就个人的理性选 择而言,检举背叛对方所得刑期,总比沉默要来得低。试设想困境中两名理性囚徒会如何作出选择:若对方沉默、背叛会让我获释,所以会选择背叛。 若对方背叛指控我,我也要指控对方才能得到较低的刑期,所以也是会选择背叛。 二人面对的情况一样,所以二人的理性思考都会得出相同的结论一一选择背叛。背叛是两种 策略之中的支配性策略。因此,这场博弈中唯一可能达到的纳什均衡,就是双方参与者都背叛对方,结果二人同样服刑2年。 例:协和谬误20 世纪60 年代,英法两国政府联合投资开发大型超音速客机,即协和飞机。该种飞机机身大、装饰豪华并且速度快,其开发可以说是一场豪赌,单是设计一个新引擎的成本就可能高达数亿元。难怪政府也会被牵涉进去,竭力要为本国企业提供更大的支持。 项目开展不久,英法两国政府发现:继续投资开发这样的机型,花费会急剧增加,但这样的设计定位能否适应市场还不知道;但是停止研制也是可怕的,因为以前的投资将付诸东流。随着研制工作的深入,他们更是无法做出停止研制工作的决定。协和飞机最终研制成功,但因飞机的缺陷(如耗油大、噪音大、污染严重等)以及运营成本太高,不适合市场竞争,英法政府为此蒙受很大的损失。

合成双语字幕

第一步:合成(分成4小步): 1. 拿到相关美剧的中文字幕和英文字幕后, 把英文字幕贴到对应的中文字幕下面(如果帖子里强调以英文时间轴为准的话,那就把中文贴到英文下,然后用srtedit软件(本贴提供下载),交换中英文字幕顺序就ok了). 偷懒小贴士:-----大家别偷这个懒了,除非已经熟练运用srtedit软件了.071207 如果拿到的中文字幕和英文字幕的时间轴差不多的话,可以用srtedit 软件初步合成中英文字幕,再手动检查. 但是软件毕竟是死的,尤其是遇到中文字幕和英文字幕时间轴差很多的话,往往会出现大量的上下句翻译错开现象,此时,就需要人工一句一句 去检查对应贴好! 有人觉得这样还不如自己一句一句老老实实手动贴 来的方便!~ 总之,选一个合适自己的方法就行了. 2. 合成好的字幕一律为SRT格式. 如果领到的中文字幕是ass格式,那就用popsub软件(问组长要)转换一下即可. 双字幕只能是两句,也就是一句中文,一句英文,中文在上面,英文在下面. 如果中文字幕是断行的,也就是有2行或者3行中文字幕,请合并回去,英文字幕也一样,实在太长的也请合并好之后留在那里,让校对人员处理.

以下是错误的双字幕: [quote]1 00:03:41,710 --> 00:03:44,700 - 怎么回事? - 没事我马上出去 - What's going on? - Nothing. I will be right out. 2 00:03:44,710 --> 00:03:46,700 好我等你 Ok, I will wait for you. 3 00:03:46,710 --> 00:03:48,700 待会见 See you later. 修改后正确的双字幕如下: 1 00:03:41,710 --> 00:03:44,700 -怎么回事? -没事我马上出去

相关文档
相关文档 最新文档